Economists Vs. Economics
Ever
since the late nineteenth century, when economics, increasingly
embracing mathematics and statistics, developed scientific pretensions,
its practitioners have been accused of a variety of sins. The charges –
including hubris, neglect of social goals beyond incomes, excessive
attention to formal techniques, and failure to predict major economic
developments such as financial crises – have usually come from
outsiders, or from a heterodox fringe. But lately it seems that even the
field’s leaders are unhappy.
Paul
Krugman, a Nobel laureate who also writes a newspaper column, has made a
habit of slamming the latest generation of models in macroeconomics
for neglecting old-fashioned Keynesian truths.
Paul Romer, one of the originators of new growth theory, has accused
some leading names, including the Nobel laureate Robert Lucas, of what he calls “mathiness” – using math to obfuscate rather than clarify.
Richard Thaler, a distinguished behavioral economist at the University of Chicago, has taken the profession to task for ignoring real-world behavior in favor of models that assume people are rational optimizers. And finance professor Luigi Zingales, also at the University of Chicago, has charged that his fellow finance specialists have led society astray by overstating the benefits produced by the financial industry.
This
kind of critical examination by the discipline’s big names is healthy
and welcome – especially in a field that has often lacked much
self-reflection. I, too, have taken aim at the discipline’s sacred cows –
free markets and free trade – often enough.
But
there is a disconcerting undertone to this new round of criticism that
needs to be made explicit – and rejected. Economics is not the kind of
science in which there could ever be one true model that works best in
all contexts. The point is not “to reach a consensus about which model
is right,” as Romer puts it, but to figure out which model applies best
in a given setting. And doing that will always remain a craft, not a
science, especially when the choice has to be made in real time.
The
social world differs from the physical world because it is man-made and
hence almost infinitely malleable. So, unlike the natural sciences,
economics advances scientifically not by replacing old models with
better ones, but by expanding its library of models, with each shedding
light on a different social contingency.
For
example, we now have many models of markets with imperfect competition
or asymmetric information. These models have not made their
predecessors, based on perfect competition, obsolete or irrelevant. They
have simply made us more aware that different circumstances call for
different models.
Similarly,
behavioral models that emphasize heuristic decision-making make us
better analysts of environments where such considerations may be
important. They do not displace rational-choice models, which remain the
go-to tool in other settings. A growth model that applies to advanced
countries may be a poor guide in developing countries. Models that
emphasize expectations are sometimes best for analyzing inflation and
unemployment levels; at other times, models with Keynesian elements will
do a superior job.
Jorge Luis Borges, the Argentine writer, once wrote a short story –
a single paragraph – that is perhaps the best guide to the scientific
method. In it, he described a distant land where cartography – the
science of making maps – was taken to ridiculous extremes. A map of a
province was so detailed that it was the size of an entire city. The map
of the empire occupied an entire province.
In
time, the cartographers became even more ambitious: they drew a map
that was an exact, one-to-one replica of the whole empire. As Borges
wryly notes, subsequent generations could find no practical use for such
an unwieldy map. So the map was left to rot in the desert, along with
the science of geography that it represented.
Borges’s point still eludes many social scientists today:
understanding requires simplification. The best way to respond to the
complexity of social life is not to devise ever-more elaborate models,
but to learn how different causal mechanisms work, one at a time, and
then figure out which ones are most relevant in a particular setting.
We
use one map if we are driving from home to work, another one if we are
traveling to another city. Yet other kinds of maps are needed if we are
on a bike, on foot, or planning to take public transport.
Navigating
among economic models – choosing which one will work better – is
considerably more difficult than choosing the right map. Practitioners
use a variety of formal and informal empirical methods with varying
skill. And, in my forthcoming book Economics Rules, I criticize economics training for not properly equipping students for the empirical diagnostics that the discipline requires.
But
the profession’s internal critics are wrong to claim that the
discipline has gone wrong because economists have yet to reach consensus
on the “correct” models (their preferred ones of course). Let us
cherish economics in all its diversity – rational and behavioral,
Keynesian and Classical, first-best and second-best, orthodox and
heterodox – and devote our energy to becoming wiser at picking which
framework to apply when.
© Project Syndicate
No comments:
Post a Comment